Results for 'Can We Believe What We Do'

994 found
Order:
  1. Francois Recanati.Can We Believe What We Do - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (1).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Can we believe what we do not understand?François Recanati - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (1):84-100.
    In a series of papers, Sperber provides the following analysis of the phenomenon of ill-understood belief (or 'quasi-belief', as I call it): (i) the quasi-believer has a validating meta-belief, to the effect that a certain representation is true; yet (ii) that representation does not give rise to a plain belief, because it is 'semi-propositional'. In this paper I discuss several aspects of this treatment. In particular, I deny that the representation accepted by the quasi-believer is semantically indeterminate, and I reject (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  3. What Do We Aim At When We Believe?Conor Mchugh - 2011 - Dialectica 65 (3):369-392.
    It is often said that belief aims at truth. I argue that if belief has an aim then that aim is knowledge rather than merely truth. My main argument appeals to the impossibility of forming a belief on the basis of evidence that only weakly favours a proposition. This phenomenon, I argue, is a problem for the truth-aim hypothesis. By contrast, it can be given a simple and satisfying explanation on the knowledge-aim hypothesis. Furthermore, the knowledge-aim hypothesis suggests a very (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  4.  15
    How Can We Believe those Stories? A Nordic Perspective The Ethical Grounds of Competing Truth-claims.Frank Bylov - 2013 - Ethics and Social Welfare 7 (3):232-240.
    This paper discusses the different, often competing, even conflicting, truth-claims that are heard around the personal narratives of marginalized, stigmatized and culturally muted people?in this case people with intellectual disabilities. Since people with intellectual disabilities began speaking up in the 1980s, tensions have emerged as to whose voice is authentic, whose story can be believed. This matters because we see the consequences of failure to believe those stories in scandals of abuse in settings, such as Winterbourne View (England) in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  25
    Can we believe what we know?Harold Morick - 1980 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 40 (3):406-410.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  89
    What can we not do at will and why.Hagit Benbaji - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (7):1941-1961.
    Recently it has been argued that we cannot intend at will. Since intentions cannot be true or false, our involuntariness cannot be traced to “the characteristic of beliefs that they aim at truth”, as Bernard Williams convincingly argues. The alternative explanation is that the source of involuntariness is the shared normative nature of beliefs and intentions. Three analogies may assimilate intentions to beliefs vis-à-vis our involuntariness: first, beliefs and intentions aim at something; second, beliefs and intentions are transparent to the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  7
    Temporal Truth and Bivalence: an Anachronistic Formal Approach to Aristotle’s De Interpretatione 9.Luiz Henrique Lopes dos Santos - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (1):59-79.
    Regarding the famous Sea Battle Argument, which Aristotle presents in De Interpretatione 9, there has never been a general agreement not only about its correctness but also, and mainly, about what the argument really is. According to the most natural reading of the chapter, the argument appeals to a temporal concept of truth and concludes that not every statement is always either true or false. However, many of Aristotle’s followers and commentators have not adopted this reading. I believe (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Can We Be Self-Deceived about What We Believe? Self-Knowledge, Self-Deception, and Rational Agency.Mathieu Doucet - 2011 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (S1):E1-E25.
    Abstract: This paper considers the question of whether it is possible to be mistaken about the content of our first-order intentional states. For proponents of the rational agency model of self-knowledge, such failures might seem very difficult to explain. On this model, the authority of self-knowledge is not based on inference from evidence, but rather originates in our capacity, as rational agents, to shape our beliefs and other intentional states. To believe that one believes that p, on this view, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  9.  21
    Why Can’t We Do What They Do? National Health Reform Abroad.Timothy Stoltzfus Jost - 2004 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 32 (3):433-441.
    Even Americans who have only a vague knowledge of health policy know that the U.S. is different. We do not have “socialized medicine,” like our European or Canadian neighbors. We believe that health care is not rationed here, and that, unlike citizens of other nations, we do not have to wait in long queues when we need medical care. We believe that U.S. health care is the best in the world.At the same time, the U.S. spends more on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10.  8
    Why Can’t We Do What They Do? National Health Reform Abroad.Timothy Stoltzfus Jost - 2004 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 32 (3):433-441.
    Even Americans who have only a vague knowledge of health policy know that the U.S. is different. We do not have “socialized medicine,” like our European or Canadian neighbors. We believe that health care is not rationed here, and that, unlike citizens of other nations, we do not have to wait in long queues when we need medical care. We believe that U.S. health care is the best in the world.At the same time, the U.S. spends more on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11. Why Do We Believe What We Are Told?Angus Ross - 1986 - Ratio (1):69-88.
    It is argued that reliance on the testimony of others cannot be viewed as reliance on a kind of evidence. Speech being essentially voluntary, the speaker cannot see his own choice of words as evidence of their truth, and so cannot honestly offer them to others as such. Rather, in taking responsibility for the truth of what he says, the speaker offers a guarantee or assurance of its truth, and in believing him the hearer accepts this assurance. I argue (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  12.  8
    What We Can Do with Words: Essays on the Relationship Between Linguistic and Non-Linguistic Theorizing.Patrick Shirreff - 2018 - Dissertation, University of Michigan
    The essays that make up my dissertation share a methodological approach that aims to explore the philosophical implications of linguists' accounts of ordinary language use. In particular, all of them focus on epistemic natural language and the implications that linguists' accounts of such language has for epistemology. The first essay focuses on the debate about the norms that govern assertion and shows the ways in which research on natural language evidentiality has direct bearing. This essay uses existing cross-linguistic data about (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  66
    Believing what we do not believe: Acquiescence to superstitious beliefs and other powerful intuitions.Jane L. Risen - 2016 - Psychological Review 123 (2):182-207.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  14.  30
    What We Can Learn From Literary Authors.Alberto Voltolini - 2021 - Acta Analytica 36 (4):479-499.
    That we can learn something from literature, as cognitivists claim, seems to be a commonplace. However, when one considers matters more deeply, it turns out to be a problematic claim. In this paper, by focusing on general revelatory facts about the world and the human spirit, I hold that the cognitivist claim can be vindicated if one takes it as follows. We do not learn such facts from literature, if by “literature” one means the truth-conditional contents that one may ascribe (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15. Can we do without pragmatic encroachment.Brian Weatherson - 2005 - Philosophical Perspectives 19 (1):417–443.
    I consider the problem of how to derive what an agent believes from their credence function and utility function. I argue the best solution of this problem is pragmatic, i.e. it is sensitive to the kinds of choices actually facing the agent. I further argue that this explains why our notion of justified belief appears to be pragmatic, as is argued e.g. by Fantl and McGrath. The notion of epistemic justification is not really a pragmatic notion, but it is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   200 citations  
  16. To what extent can we overcome the „bystander effects‟ of collective responsibility in matters of global injustice?“.Isabelle Baker - 2011 - Emergent Australasian Philosophers 4 (1).
    Where do we draw the line between individual and collective responsibilities? Can collectives be „morally responsible‟ in the same way that individuals can? This paper explores the Bystander Effect – how an individual‟s sense of personal responsibility can become „diffused‟ when they become part of a collective. This is compared to the issue of the collective responsibility of the „developed world‟ to aid the „Third World‟ that ethicists, such Peter Singer and Iris Marion Young believe to be true. I (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. What can we Know a priori?Carrie Jenkins - unknown
    Michael Devitt has been developing an influential two-pronged attack on the a priori for over thirteen years. This attack does not attempt to undermine the coherence or significance of the distinction between the a priori and the a posteriori, but rather to answer the question: 'What Can We Know A Priori?' with: 'Nothing'. In this paper I explain why I am dissatisfied with key extant responses to Devitt's attack, and then take my own steps towards resisting the attack as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  17
    What Do We Do about Bleakness?Alan Holland - 2011 - Environmental Values 20 (3):315 - 321.
    In response to Robin Attfield, I am inclined, still, (a) to claim that the concept of value cannot do the kind of comparative work that he asks it to do; (b) to doubt that the value of our world can be founded on the flourishing to be found there; and (c) to believe that there is enough in the world to be glad about even if it does not contain a preponderance of value. In response to John Cottingham, (a) (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19. Epistemic Paradise Lost: Saving What We Can with Stable Support.Anna-Maria A. Eder - 2021 - In Nick Hughes (ed.), Epistemic Dilemmas. Oxford University Press.
    I focus on the No-Paradise Dilemma, which results from some initially plausible epistemic ideals, coupled with an assumption concerning our evidence. Our evidence indicates that we are not in an epistemic paradise, in which we do not experience cognitive failures. I opt for a resolution of the dilemma that is based on an evidentialist position that can be motivated independently of the dilemma. According to this position, it is rational for an agent to believe a proposition on the agent’s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  4
    A comprehensive history of Western ethics: what do we believe?Warren Ashby - 2005 - Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books. Edited by W. Allen Ashby.
    "Ashby includes the great thinkers and periods that have shaped Western ethics: the Greeks, the Hebrew prophets, the Roman Stoics, St. Augustine, the medieval ethicists, the Renaissance and Reformation, the Enlightenment, the Romantics, and the radical revolutions of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. In the period from 1850 to 1920, Ashby notes, the transformations wrought by the four great modern thinkers - Darwim, Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud - both extended and significantly challenged the traditional core beliefs of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Gathering the godless: intentional "communities" and ritualizing ordinary life. Section Three.Cultural Production : Learning to Be Cool, or Making Due & What We Do - 2015 - In Anthony B. Pinn (ed.), Humanism: essays on race, religion and cultural production. London: Bloomsbury Academic, an imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  11
    The grand delusion: what we know but don't believe.Steve Hagen - 2020 - Somerville, MA, USA: Wisdom Publications.
    Robert Pirsig wrote of Steve Hagen's first book, Why the World Doesn't Seem to Make Sense, "For those who are certain that objectivity and intellect are the ground floor of all knowledge, this can be a valuable trip to the sub-basement." Now, in The Grand Delusion, Hagen drills deeper, into the most basic strengths, assumptions, and limitations of religion and belief, philosophy and inquiry, science, and technology. In doing so, he shines new light on the question Why is there Something (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Why believe what people say?Leslie Stevenson - 1993 - Synthese 94 (3):429 - 451.
    The basic alternatives seem to be either a Humean reductionist view that any particular assertion needs backing with inductive evidence for its reliability before it can retionally be believed, or a Reidian criterial view that testimony is intrinscially, though defeasibly, credible, in the absence of evidence against its reliability.Some recent arguments from the constraints on interpreting any linguistic performances as assertions with propositional content have some force against the reductionist view. We thus have reason to accept the criterial view, at (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  24.  4
    What can we believe?Vergilius Ture Anselm Ferm - 1948 - New York,: Philosophical Library.
  25.  14
    What Can We Believe.Peter A. Bertocci - 1950 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 10 (4):597-598.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. What may we believe? What ought we to do?T. Spitzley, M. Holtje & W. Spohn (eds.) - 2013
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  20
    Do Retinal Neurons Also Represent Somatosensory Inputs? On Why Neuronal Responses Are Not Sufficient to Determine What Neurons Do.Lotem Elber-Dorozko & Yonatan Loewenstein - 2023 - Cognitive Science 47 (4):e13265.
    How does neuronal activity give rise to cognitive capacities? To address this question, neuroscientists hypothesize about what neurons “represent,” “encode,” or “compute,” and test these hypotheses empirically. This process is similar to the assessment of hypotheses in other fields of science and as such is subject to the same limitations and difficulties that have been discussed at length by philosophers of science. In this paper, we highlight an additional difficulty in the process of empirical assessment of hypotheses that is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  41
    What can we be forced to do?Gerald Dworkin - 1991 - Journal of Social Philosophy 22 (2):40-48.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Can We Believe the Error Theory?Bart Streumer - 2013 - Journal of Philosophy 110 (4):194-212.
    According to the error theory, normative judgements are beliefs that ascribe normative properties, even though such properties do not exist. In this paper, I argue that we cannot believe the error theory, and that this means that there is no reason for us to believe this theory. It may be thought that this is a problem for the error theory, but I argue that it is not. Instead, I argue, our inability to believe the error theory undermines (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  30.  34
    Can We Forget What We Know in a False‐Belief Task? An Investigation of the True‐Belief Default.Paula Rubio-Fernández - 2017 - Cognitive Science 41 (1):218-241.
    It has been generally assumed in the Theory of Mind literature of the past 30 years that young children fail standard false-belief tasks because they attribute their own knowledge to the protagonist. Contrary to the traditional view, we have recently proposed that the children's bias is task induced. This alternative view was supported by studies showing that 3 year olds are able to pass a false-belief task that allows them to focus on the protagonist, without drawing their attention to the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  20
    How we remember what we can do.Gunnar Declerck - 2015 - Socioaffective Neuroscience and Psychology 5.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32. Who knows what and who can we believe? Epistemological beliefs are beliefs about knowledge (mostly) to be attained from others.Rainer Bromme, Dorothe Kienhues & Torsten Porsch - 2010 - In Lisa D. Bendixen & Florian C. Feucht (eds.), Personal epistemology in the classroom: theory, research, and implications for practice. New York: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33.  30
    What did Hume reauy show about induction? Samir Okasha.What Compositionality StiU Can Do - 2001 - Philosophy 76 (295):479-480.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  68
    The Evidential Argument from Goodness.Wes Morriston - 2004 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 42 (1):87-101.
    severe and prolonged pain, in heartbreak and destruction, in disloyalty and betrayal, in the suffering of the innocent, in unjust punishment. He has, in short, an intense dislike for anything that you or I might approve of or enjoy. If he had his druthers we'd all be utterly miserable and come to a bad end. Now I' ve certainly never met a demonist, and I suppose we can agree that demonism would be an extraordinarily implausible view. Still, it is worth (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  35.  4
    God of our fathers?: do we know what we believe?Peter Vardy - 1987 - London: Darton, Longman, and Todd.
  36.  69
    Heidegger on ontological education, or: How we become what we are.Iain Thomson - 2001 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 44 (3):243 – 268.
    Heidegger presciently diagnosed the current crisis in higher education. Contemporary theorists like Bill Readings extend and update Heidegger's critique, documenting the increasing instrumentalization, professionalization, vocationalization, corporatization, and technologization of the modern university, the dissolution of its unifying and guiding ideals, and, consequently, the growing hyper-specialization and ruinous fragmentation of its departments. Unlike Heidegger, however, these critics do not recognize such disturbing trends as interlocking symptoms of an underlying ontological problem and so they provide no positive vision for the future of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  37. Causal powers: what are they? why do we need them? what can be done with them and what cannot?Nancy Cartwright - unknown
    What are causal powers and why should we believe in them? Causal powers are now a central topic in metaphysics but my defence of them does not begin there, but rather in studies of the practices of the sciences, especially in my case, of physics and economics. Both of these use the analytic method: they ascertain the behaviour that would result from the operation of a cause ‘in isolation’; then take this behaviour to provide the ‘contribution’ that that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38. The moral obligations of reasonable non-believers: A special problem for divine command metaethics.Wes Morriston - 2009 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 65 (1):1 - 10.
    People who do not believe that there is a God constitute an obvious problem for divine command metaethics. They have moral obligations, and are often enough aware of having them. Yet it is not easy to think of such persons as “hearing” divine commands. This makes it hard to see how a divine command theory can offer a completely general account of the nature of moral obligation. The present paper takes a close look at this issue as it emerges (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39. What we do and presuppose when we demonstrate.Eduarda Calado Barbosa & Felipe Nogueira De Carvalho - 2021 - Veritas – Revista de Filosofia da Pucrs 65 (3):e38525.
    In this paper, we defend that demonstratives are expressions of joint attention. Though this idea is not exactly new in the philosophical or linguistic literature, we argue here that their proponents have not yet shown how to incorporate these observations into more traditional theories of demonstratives. Our purpose is then to attempt to fill this gap. We argue that coordinated attentional activities are better integrated into a full account of demonstratives as meta-pragmatic information. Our claim is twofold. First, we claim (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. What do we see (when we do)?Sean D. Kelly - 1999 - In Thomas Baldwin (ed.), Philosophical Topics. Routledge. pp. 107-128.
    1. The philosophical problem of what we see My topic revolves around what is apparently a very basic question. Stripped of all additions and in its leanest, most economical form, this is the question: "What do we see?" But in this most basic form the question admits of at least three different interpretations. In the first place, one might understand it to be an epistemological question, perhaps one with skeptical overtones. "What do we see?", on this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  41.  21
    To What Inanimate Matter Are We Most Closely Related and Does the Origin of Life Harbor Meaning?William F. Martin, Falk S. P. Nagies & Andrey do Nascimento Vieira - 2021 - Philosophies 6 (2):33.
    The question concerning the meaning of life is important, but it immediately confronts the present authors with insurmountable obstacles from a philosophical standpoint, as it would require us to define not only what we hold to be life, but what we hold to be meaning in addition, requiring us to do both in a properly researched context. We unconditionally surrender to that challenge. Instead, we offer a vernacular, armchair approach to life’s origin and meaning, with some layman’s thoughts (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  40
    Comparative effectiveness research: what to do when experts disagree about risks.Reidar K. Lie, Francis K. L. Chan, Christine Grady, Vincent H. Ng & David Wendler - 2017 - BMC Medical Ethics 18 (1):42.
    Ethical issues related to comparative effectiveness research, or research that compares existing standards of care, have recently received considerable attention. In this paper we focus on how Ethics Review Committees should evaluate the risks of comparative effectiveness research. We discuss what has been a prominent focus in the debate about comparative effectiveness research, namely that it is justified when “nothing is known” about the comparative effectiveness of the available alternatives. We argue that this focus may be misleading. Rather, we (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Must the Beginning of the Universe Have a Personal Cause?Wes Morriston - 2000 - Faith and Philosophy 17 (2):149-169.
    The aim of this paper is to take a close look at some little discussed aspects of the kalam cosmological argument, with a view to deciding whether there is any reason to believe the causal principle on which it rests (“Whatever begins to exist must have a cause”), and also with a view to determining what conclusions can be drawn about the nature of the First Cause of the universe (supposing thatthere is one). I am particularly concerned with (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  44.  82
    Must the Beginning of the Universe Have a Personal Cause?Wes Morriston - 2000 - Faith and Philosophy 17 (2):149-169.
    The aim of this paper is to take a close look at some little discussed aspects of the kalam cosmological argument, with a view to deciding whether there is any reason to believe the causal principle on which it rests (“Whatever begins to exist must have a cause”), and also with a view to determining what conclusions can be drawn about the nature of the First Cause of the universe (supposing thatthere is one). I am particularly concerned with (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  45. When do we stop digging? Conditions on a fundamental theory of physics.Karen Crowther - 2019 - In Anthony Aguirre, Brendan Foster & Zeeya Merali (eds.), What is Fundamental? Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 123-133.
    In seeking an answer to the question of what it means for a theory to be fundamental, it is enlightening to ask why the current best theories of physics are not generally believed to be fundamental. This reveals a set of conditions that a theory of physics must satisfy in order to be considered fundamental. Physics aspires to describe ever deeper levels of reality, which may be without end. Ultimately, at any stage we may not be able to tell (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  46.  45
    Explanatory Priority and the Counterfactuals of Freedom.Wes Morriston - 2001 - Faith and Philosophy 18 (1):21-35.
    On a Molinist account of creation and providence, not only is there is a complete set of truths about what every possible person would freely do in any possible set of circumstances, but these conditional truths are part of the very explanation of our existence. Robert Adams has recently argued that the explanatory priority of these conditionals undermines libertarian freedom. In the present essay, I take at close look at Adams’ argument and at the Molinist response of Thomas Flint. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  47.  2
    Doing what's right: how to fight for what you believe-- and make a difference.Tavis Smiley - 2000 - New York: Doubleday.
    Black Entertainment Television (BET) talk show host Tavis Smiley, in an impassioned call to arms, sets forth the tools we can use to stand up for what we believe in and help transform our communities, our lives, and our world. Tavis Smiley isn't alone in pointing out that our neighborhoods are unsafe, our communities are unraveling, and our most basic values--civility, a sense of justice, integrity, and responsibility--are under attack, from the Oval Office to the corner office. But (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  3
    Hands: What We Do with Them – and Why vol. 1.Darian Leader - 2016 - Penguin Books.
    A fresh, thought-provoking and wide-ranging study of how mankind uses its hands Why do zombies walk with their arms outstretched? How can newborn babies grip an adult finger tightly enough to dangle unsupported from it? And why is everyone constantly texting, tapping and scrolling? For anyone curious about how human beings work, the answers are hidden in plain sight: in our hands. From early tools to machinery -- from fists to knives to guns -- from papyrus to QWERTY to a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Telling Others to Do What You Believe Is Morally Wrong: The Case of Confucius and Zai Wo.Frederick Choo - 2019 - Asian Philosophy 29 (2):106-115.
    Can it ever be morally justifiable to tell others to do what we ourselves believe is morally wrong to do? The common sense answer is no. It seems that we should never tell others to do something if we think it is morally wrong to do that act. My first goal is to argue that in Analects 17.21, Confucius tells his disciple not to observe a ritual even though Confucius himself believes that it is morally wrong that one (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  23
    On the Priority of the Right to the Good. Do&Gbreve & Aysel an - 2011 - Kant Studien 102 (3):316-334.
    Rawls's view that the right is prior to the good has been criticized by various scholars from divergent points of view. Some contend that Rawls's teleological/deontological distinction based on the priority of the right is misleading while others claim that no plausible ethical theory can determine what is right prior to the good. There is no consensus on how to interpret the priority of right to the good; nor is there an agreement on the criteria of teleological/deontological distinction. In (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 994